Subscribe to the PwC Newsletter
Join the community, edit social preview.
Add a new code entry for this paper
Remove a code repository from this paper, mark the official implementation from paper authors, add a new evaluation result row.
TASK | DATASET | MODEL | METRIC NAME | METRIC VALUE | GLOBAL RANK | REMOVE |
---|
Remove a task
Add a method, remove a method, edit datasets, experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world.
13 Feb 2019 · Massimiliano Proietti , Alexander Pickston , Francesco Graffitti , Peter Barrow , Dmytro Kundys , Cyril Branciard , Martin Ringbauer , Alessandro Fedrizzi · Edit social preview
The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally, independently of who observed them. In quantum mechanics, the objectivity of observations is not so clear, most dramatically exposed in Eugene Wigner's eponymous thought experiment where two observers can experience fundamentally different realities. While observer-independence has long remained inaccessible to empirical investigation, recent no-go-theorems construct an extended Wigner's friend scenario with four entangled observers that allows us to put it to the test. In a state-of-the-art 6-photon experiment, we here realise this extended Wigner's friend scenario, experimentally violating the associated Bell-type inequality by 5 standard deviations. This result lends considerable strength to interpretations of quantum theory already set in an observer-dependent framework and demands for revision of those which are not.
Code Edit Add Remove Mark official
- Social Psychology
- Rejection (Psychology)
Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world
- February 2019
- Heriot-Watt University
- This person is not on ResearchGate, or hasn't claimed this research yet.
Discover the world's research
- 25+ million members
- 160+ million publication pages
- 2.3+ billion citations
No file available
To read the file of this research, you can request a copy directly from the authors.
- OPT EXPRESS
- Alessandro Fedrizzi
- Jian-Wei Pan
- Anton Zeilinger
- Karl Popper
- Arthur Fine
- David Deutsch
- Thomas Herbst
- D Frauchiger
- PHYS REV LETT
- F Graffitti
- J Kelly-Massicotte
- A M Brańczyk
- T Yamashita
- J.-Å Larsson
- G C Ghirardi
- REV MOD PHYS
- H I Everett
- INT J THEOR PHYS
- J Calsamiglia
- N Lutkenhaus
- S L Braunstein
- P H Eberhard
- Recruit researchers
- Join for free
- Login Email Tip: Most researchers use their institutional email address as their ResearchGate login Password Forgot password? Keep me logged in Log in or Continue with Google Welcome back! Please log in. Email · Hint Tip: Most researchers use their institutional email address as their ResearchGate login Password Forgot password? Keep me logged in Log in or Continue with Google No account? Sign up
Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser .
Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.
- We're Hiring!
- Help Center
Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world
The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally, independently of who observed them. In quantum mechanics, the objectivity of observations is not so clear, most dramatically exposed in Eugene Wigner's eponymous thought experiment where two observers can experience fundamentally different realities. While observer-independence has long remained inaccessible to empirical investigation, recent no-go-theorems construct an extended Wigner's friend scenario with four entangled observers that allows us to put it to the test. In a state-of-the-art 6-photon experiment, we here realise this extended Wigner's friend scenario, experimentally violating the associated Bell-type inequality by 5 standard deviations. This result lends considerable strength to interpretations of quantum theory already set in an observer-dependent framework and demands for revision of those which are not.
Related Papers
Eric Cavalcanti
Does quantum theory apply at all scales, including that of observers? A resurgence of interest in the long-standing Wigner's friend paradox has shed new light on this fundamental question. Here---building on a scenario with two separated but entangled "friends" introduced by Brukner---we rigorously prove that if quantum evolution is controllable on the scale of an observer, then one of the following three assumptions must be false: "No-Superdeterminism", "Locality", or "Absoluteness of Observed Events" (i.e. that every observed event exists absolutely, not relatively). We show that although the violation of Bell-type inequalities in such scenarios is not in general sufficient to demonstrate the contradiction between those assumptions, new inequalities can be derived, in a theory-independent manner, which are violated by quantum correlations. We demonstrate this in a proof-of-principle experiment where a photon's path is deemed an obser...
Conference on Lasers and Electro-Optics
The Wigner’s friend paradox illuminates the quantum measurement problem. We derive—and study, in a series of entangled-photon experiments—a new and robust no-go theorem based on the paradox, with stronger constraints than Bell's theorem.
AOS Australian Conference on Optical Fibre Technology (ACOFT) and Australian Conference on Optics, Lasers, and Spectroscopy (ACOLS) 2019
Bahram Borgheai
arXiv (Cornell University)
Foundations of Physics
Tony Sudbery
Journal of Optics B: Quantum and Semiclassical Optics
joseph samuel
Gregg Jaeger
Philosophy of Science
Richard Healey
Physical review letters
Waldimar Amaya
Local realism is the worldview in which physical properties of objects exist independently of measurement and where physical influences cannot travel faster than the speed of light. Bell's theorem states that this worldview is incompatible with the predictions of quantum mechanics, as is expressed in Bell's inequalities. Previous experiments convincingly supported the quantum predictions. Yet, every experiment requires assumptions that provide loopholes for a local realist explanation. Here, we report a Bell test that closes the most significant of these loopholes simultaneously. Using a well-optimized source of entangled photons, rapid setting generation, and highly efficient superconducting detectors, we observe a violation of a Bell inequality with high statistical significance. The purely statistical probability of our results to occur under local realism does not exceed 3.74×10^{-31}, corresponding to an 11.5 standard deviation effect.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
RELATED PAPERS
Cornell University - arXiv
Channa Hatharasinghe
Christopher Altman
Old and New Concepts of Physics
Vladimir K Ignatovich
Journal of Modern Physics
María Esther Burgos L
Contemporary Physics
Nuriya Nurgalieva
Laurens Walleghem
Adrian Ortega
Physical Review A
Physical Review Letters
Chau Nguyen
Advanced Science Letters
Marek Zukowski
Fabrizio Bisesto
Handbook of Natural Computing
Inge Helland
Foundations of Physics - FOUND PHYS
Fred Kuttner
Willem de Muynck
Nature Communications
Pierfrancesco La Mura , Aleksander Marcin Kubicki
Physics Letters A
Koji Nagata
SSRN Electronic Journal
Chris Thron
Edward T . H . Wu
- We're Hiring!
- Help Center
- Find new research papers in:
- Health Sciences
- Earth Sciences
- Cognitive Science
- Mathematics
- Computer Science
- Academia ©2024
- Newsletters
A quantum experiment suggests there’s no such thing as objective reality
- Emerging Technology from the arXiv archive page
Back in 1961, the Nobel Prize–winning physicist Eugene Wigner outlined a thought experiment that demonstrated one of the lesser-known paradoxes of quantum mechanics. The experiment shows how the strange nature of the universe allows two observers—say, Wigner and Wigner’s friend—to experience different realities.
Since then, physicists have used the “Wigner’s Friend” thought experiment to explore the nature of measurement and to argue over whether objective facts can exist. That’s important because scientists carry out experiments to establish objective facts. But if they experience different realities, the argument goes, how can they agree on what these facts might be?
That’s provided some entertaining fodder for after-dinner conversation, but Wigner’s thought experiment has never been more than that—just a thought experiment.
Last year, however, physicists noticed that recent advances in quantum technologies have made it possible to reproduce the Wigner’s Friend test in a real experiment. In other words, it ought to be possible to create different realities and compare them in the lab to find out whether they can be reconciled.
And today, Massimiliano Proietti at Heriot-Watt University in Edinburgh and a few colleagues say they have performed this experiment for the first time: they have created different realities and compared them. Their conclusion is that Wigner was correct—these realities can be made irreconcilable so that it is impossible to agree on objective facts about an experiment.
Wigner’s original thought experiment is straightforward in principle. It begins with a single polarized photon that, when measured, can have either a horizontal polarization or a vertical polarization. But before the measurement, according to the laws of quantum mechanics, the photon exists in both polarization states at the same time—a so-called superposition.
Wigner imagined a friend in a different lab measuring the state of this photon and storing the result, while Wigner observed from afar. Wigner has no information about his friend’s measurement and so is forced to assume that the photon and the measurement of it are in a superposition of all possible outcomes of the experiment.
Wigner can even perform an experiment to determine whether this superposition exists or not. This is a kind of interference experiment showing that the photon and the measurement are indeed in a superposition.
From Wigner’s point of view, this is a “fact”—the superposition exists. And this fact suggests that a measurement cannot have taken place.
But this is in stark contrast to the point of view of the friend, who has indeed measured the photon’s polarization and recorded it. The friend can even call Wigner and say the measurement has been done (provided the outcome is not revealed).
So the two realities are at odds with each other. “This calls into question the objective status of the facts established by the two observers,” say Proietti and co.
That’s the theory, but last year Caslav Brukner, at the University of Vienna in Austria, came up with a way to re-create the Wigner’s Friend experiment in the lab by means of techniques involving the entanglement of many particles at the same time.
The breakthrough that Proietti and co have made is to carry this out. “In a state-of-the-art 6-photon experiment, we realize this extended Wigner’s friend scenario,” they say.
They use these six entangled photons to create two alternate realities—one representing Wigner and one representing Wigner’s friend. Wigner’s friend measures the polarization of a photon and stores the result. Wigner then performs an interference measurement to determine if the measurement and the photon are in a superposition.
The experiment produces an unambiguous result. It turns out that both realities can coexist even though they produce irreconcilable outcomes, just as Wigner predicted.
That raises some fascinating questions that are forcing physicists to reconsider the nature of reality.
The idea that observers can ultimately reconcile their measurements of some kind of fundamental reality is based on several assumptions. The first is that universal facts actually exist and that observers can agree on them.
But there are other assumptions too. One is that observers have the freedom to make whatever observations they want. And another is that the choices one observer makes do not influence the choices other observers make—an assumption that physicists call locality.
If there is an objective reality that everyone can agree on, then these assumptions all hold.
But Proietti and co’s result suggests that objective reality does not exist. In other words, the experiment suggests that one or more of the assumptions—the idea that there is a reality we can agree on, the idea that we have freedom of choice, or the idea of locality—must be wrong.
Of course, there is another way out for those hanging on to the conventional view of reality. This is that there is some other loophole that the experimenters have overlooked. Indeed, physicists have tried to close loopholes in similar experiments for years, although they concede that it may never be possible to close them all.
Nevertheless, the work has important implications for the work of scientists. “The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally, independently of who observed them,” say Proietti and co. And yet in the same paper, they undermine this idea, perhaps fatally.
The next step is to go further: to construct experiments creating increasingly bizarre alternate realities that cannot be reconciled. Where this will take us is anybody’s guess. But Wigner, and his friend, would surely not be surprised.
Ref: arxiv.org/abs/1902.05080 : Experimental Rejection of Observer-Independence in the Quantum World
Keep Reading
Most popular.
Why OpenAI’s new model is such a big deal
The bulk of LLM progress until now has been language-driven. This new model enters the realm of complex reasoning, with implications for physics, coding, and more.
- James O'Donnell archive page
A controversial Chinese CRISPR scientist is still hopeful about embryo gene editing. Here’s why.
He Jiankui, who went to prison for three years for making the world’s first gene-edited babies, talked to MIT Technology Review about his new research plans.
- Zeyi Yang archive page
Meet the radio-obsessed civilian shaping Ukraine’s drone defense
Since Russia’s invasion, Serhii “Flash” Beskrestnov has become an influential, if sometimes controversial, force—sharing expert advice and intel on the ever-evolving technology that’s taken over the skies. His work may determine the future of Ukraine, and wars far beyond it.
- Charlie Metcalfe archive page
Two Nobel Prize winners want to cancel their own CRISPR patents in Europe
There’s a surprise twist in the battle to control genome editing.
- Antonio Regalado archive page
Stay connected
Get the latest updates from mit technology review.
Discover special offers, top stories, upcoming events, and more.
Thank you for submitting your email!
It looks like something went wrong.
We’re having trouble saving your preferences. Try refreshing this page and updating them one more time. If you continue to get this message, reach out to us at [email protected] with a list of newsletters you’d like to receive.
IEEE Account
- Change Username/Password
- Update Address
Purchase Details
- Payment Options
- Order History
- View Purchased Documents
Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world
- observer-dependece
Paper Review: Experimental Rejection of Observer-independence in the Quantum World
The MIT Technology Review recently published an article entitled “ A quantum experiment suggests there’s no such thing as objective reality “. This sounds rather spicy: if this were true, and there were no objective reality, what would that mean? Would the postmodernists be right? Would it all be purely subjective? How about claims like “there is no objective reality”–is that an objective fact? If not, how does this all hang together?
Maybe you think this is a case of the media blowing something out of proportion, or getting the science wrong. Surely the title of the original paper is something esoteric and boring like “K-alpha particles exhibit decoherence along mesa-keta spectra at 196mmz intervals” or some other Star Trek made up sounding jargon. But then you look at the title of the paper:
“ Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world “
Uh-oh. This sounds like a ( rare? ) case where maybe the media are actually reporting accurately on the science—the title would certainly suggest that the scientists believe their experiment rejects objective reality, or something like that. Maybe this is just the scientists selling the paper? So then you read the abstract:
“The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally, independently of who observed them. In quantum mechanics, the objectivity of observations is not so clear, most dramatically exposed in Eugene Wigner’s eponymous thought experiment where two observers can experience fundamentally different realities. While observer-independence has long remained inaccessible to empirical investigation, recent no-go-theorems construct an extended Wigner’s friend scenario with four entangled observers that allows us to put it to the test. In a state-of-the-art 6-photon experiment, we here realise this extended Wigner’s friend scenario, experimentally violating the associated Bell-type inequality by 5 standard deviations. This result lends considerable strength to interpretations of quantum theory already set in an observer-dependent framework and demands for revision of those which are not.”
Hmm. Well. The scientists themselves do in fact seem to be claiming that their experiment gives strong support for an observer-dependent, entirely subjective reality. Even if we wanted to read charitably, and think that this kind of subjectivity was something less exotic and threatening to science, like the kind of observer dependent properties of relativity , we reread the first line of the abstract. The kind of objective facts the authors seem to have in mind are the kind that make science possible. This suggests a much deeper rejection of an objective world than the kind found in relativity (which does not in fact reject an object world, but merely has no privileged reference frame ).
Let us take a closer look at the actual text of the paper, then. Throughout my analysis I will also reference the latest entry of the “ Philosopher’s On ” series of the philosophy site Daily Nous . I’ll link to it a few more times throughout the paper. I’d recommend anyone reading my post, which in some ways takes a bit of a deeper dive into the content of the paper, to read the Daily Nous post after. It is very helpful and enlightening.
When talking about the experiment (which I will discuss in a minute) the scientists write, suggestively, “Can one reconcile their different records, or are they fundamentally incompatible—so that they cannot be considered objective, observer-independent ‘facts of the world’?” (p. 2). They will claim later in the paper that the answer is likely “no”. Indeed, they write in their conclusion:
“Modulo the potential loopholes and accepting the photons’ status as observers, the violation of inequality (2) implies that at least one of the three assumptions of free choice, locality, and observer-independent facts must fail…[one] option is to give up observer independence completely by considering facts only relative to observers…This choice, however, requires us to embrace the possibility that different observers irreconcilably disagree about what happened in an experiment.” (p. 4)
The sections over which I elided describe the other options; options which I will later argue are better. However, it is clear that the conclusion these scientists prefer is to give up an objective, observer independent world. Why is this?
To understand their argument, first we should understand a few things from the previous excerpt: what exactly was the experiment? What are the three conditions–free choice, locality, and observer-independent facts?
The experiment they conducted was a modification of the famous Wigner’s Friend thought experiment.
Wigner asks us to consider a physical system prepared in a superposition. For example, the system might be an electron, and the electron might be in a superposition of being spin-up and spin-down. What exactly is a superposition? I think an example might be helpful: consider the case in which we are interested in the location of an electron. In particular, we want to know if it in a certain room, or outside the room. We can represent the particle and its room-position (which is a binary observable with two possible values: in the room and out of the room ) using the mathematics of quantum mechanics. There is a rule in quantum mechanics called the eigenstate-eigenvalue link (see here for an introduction and history of the rule), that says that the particle has a room-position if and only if the mathematical vector describing the physical system is in an eigenstate of the mathematical object describing room-position observable. This sounds technical, so let’s unpack it a little. Suppose we have a clock:
We can think of the clock as being a Hilbert Space — mathematical object physicists use to describe the state of a physical system. How do we represent whether the particle is in or out of the room? We represent such a property using two vectors at right angles to each other. For example, the two vectors very sketchily drawn here:
The vertical line might represent being in the room, and the horizontal one out of the room. Suppose the state of the particle is represented by the minute hand. The eigenstate-eigenvalue link says that the particle has a position if and only if the minute hand lies on one of the blue lines. In this case, since the minute hand does not lie on one of the blue lines, the particle does not have a position! In this case, we say that the particle is in a superposition of being in the room and out of the room. What is important to note is that even though the particle does not have a definite position, it does have a state–the one represented by the minute hand. In principle, we could design a measuring device to see whether that particle is in that state. This means we can measure whether or not the particle is in a superposition.
Thus, like in the above picture, it can be false that the particle is either in the room or out of the room. Note this is not a contradiction. It is true that the particle is not in the room, and it is not out of the room. However, these are not the only two possibilities. Instead, as I said above, we describe the particle as being in a superposition of being in the room and out of the room. This might be rather shocking, since it seems to defy classical logic. However, it does not. It is rather analogous to a case in which someone believes that every object is either black or white. Thus, for a person with such a conception of colour, the statement “every object is either black or white” seems tautologically true. However, one day this person encounters a red rose. For this person, this might initially feel like a violation of logic. However, upon reflection, she comes to the realization that instead of violating logic, this observation instead demonstrated that she had had an incorrect theory of the possible colours an object might be. The case is the same in quantum mechanics. The electron lacking a position does not defy logic; we rather have to enlarge our initially impoverished space of possible properties.
So, for the Wigner’s Friend thought experiment, we have a particle in a superposition of some property–say, X-spin. Furthermore, suppose we have an observer–Wigner. Since Wigner is a physical system, we can describe him using the mathematics of quantum mechanics. Suppose the friend is to measure the particle, and then Wigner is to measure whether or not his friend and the physical system are in a superposition. Here is how the scientists describe the thought experiment (edited a little to remove some of the math; edits marked with “[*]”):
“According to quantum theory, the friend randomly observes one of the two possible outcomes in every run of the experiment. The friend’s record, [up] or [down], can be stored in one of two possible orthogonal states of some physical memory, labeled either [“electron is up”] or [“electron is down”], and constitutes a “fact” from the friend’s point of view. Wigner observes from outside the isolated laboratory and has no information about his friend’s measurement outcome. According to quantum theory Wigner must describe the friend’s measurement as a unitary interaction that leaves the photon and friend’s record [an] the entangled state… Wigner can now perform an interference experiment in this entangled basis to verify that the photon and his friend’s record are indeed in superposition—a “fact” from his point of view, from which he concludes that his friend cannot have recorded a definite outcome. Concurrently however, the friend does always record a definite outcome, which suggests that the original superposition was destroyed and Wigner should not observe any interference. The friend can even tell Wigner that she recorded a definite outcome (without revealing the result), yet Wigner and his friend’s respective descriptions remain unchanged [6]. This calls into question the objective status of the facts established by the two observers” (pp. 1-2)
This is the tension: from the friend’s perspective, the electron has a determinate X-spin. From Wigner’s, however, the friend and the particle are in a superposition. Thus, the reasoning in this paper goes, there is no objective reality (or at the very least this is called into question).
The actual experiment that the scientists performed is not exactly Wigner’s friend, but what they call an extension of Wigner’s friend. There is another famous type of experiment in quantum mechanics that is meant to confirm the violation of something called a Bell-type inequality . Named after John Bell, he used it to prove his famous theorem , which states that any physical theory that reproduces the probabilistic predictions of quantum mechanics will have to reject a locality condition (to be discussed shortly). There is a vast literature on what exactly Bell’s theorem(s) shows. However, what is important to note here is that this is a well-knows result that has been empirically confirmed many times. What I mean by this is that the kind of probabilistic predictions used in Bell’s theorem have been empirically confirmed to be the optimal predictions we could make (of course things are a little more subtle, but this is the gist–quantum mechanics is the most successful physical theory we have ever written down; as Everett put it, “This formulation describes a wealth of experience. No experimental evidence is known which contradicts it.”).
The experiment discussed in the paper is a combination of Wigner’s friend and the kind of experiment used to test whether Bell’s equality is violated (which is what quantum mechanics predicts). However, the key thing that the experiments were after was whether or not there are “observer-independent fact”–this depends much more on the Wignerian aspect of their experiment than the Bell aspect. (Indeed, it seems to me, and others I will point to later, is that combining these two is a kind of red herring, and is uninteresting.) Karen Crowther on Daily Nous gives a good description of the actual experiment:
“Now, what the experiment actually did was to use QM to calculate the probabilities of each of the possible measurement outcomes, and then compare these to the probabilities calculated from the experimental data obtained (1794 six-photon coincidence events, using 64 settings, over a total of 360 hours). The experimenters did this in order to test the violation of a Bell-type inequality, and the experiment was indeed successful in confirming its violation.”
So, we have a decent understanding now of what the experiment was. Whether or not this experiments actually lends support to what the scientists claim it does, I will leave for later. For now let’s get a handle on the three conditions needed for their theoretical result: free choice, locality, and observer-independent facts.
I’ve actually discussed the free choice condition on this blog before , so I won’t go into too much detail (this will be a long enough post already). The key idea is that the observers of the experiment can freely choose which property of the physical system to measure: there are no conspiracies of physics in which the experiments are bound to measure certain properties so that the results come out just so. Again, for an extended discussion, see the previous post.
The locality condition means that distant measurements (and physical systems in general) cannot affect each other. For example, if I measure the property of a physical system over at Alpha Centauri, it should not instantaneously affect a system you want to measure on Earth. This is somewhat motivated by wanting a quantum mechanics to be consistent with special relativity which imposes a kind of locality constraint, and somewhat motivated by intuition. However, almost every theory of quantum mechanics violates locality; it seems to be something we might have to give up. We’ll discuss this point more a little later.
The final condition is “observer independent facts”. The paper is a little vague and unclear about what this means. Thus from the paper itself it is unclear how this requirement interacts with their result. However, in one of the papers that the experimental paper cites, the condition is specified more clearly. Put plainly, this assumption is that “One can jointly assign truth values to the propositions about observed outcomes (“facts”) of different observers” (p. 5 from the paper linked immediately above). The paper also gives a slightly more technical account of this postulate, but this is sufficient for our purposes here.
Now we have a handle on the experiment, and the three conditions needed for the “no-go theorem for observer-independent facts” which the experiments are trying to empirically support. What is their argument, and is it successful?
Recall from the earlier quote from the conclusion of the paper. The theorem says that accepting the conditions of free choice, locality, and observer independent facts is incompatible with their experiments results, since they violate the Bell-type inequality. This much is true. Thus, we must give up one. Which one? They argue for giving up observer-independent facts. However their argument is rather sparse; they briefly mention that “one way to accommodate our result is by proclaiming that ‘facts of the world’ can only be established by a privileged observer—e.g., one that would have access to the ‘global wavefunction’ in the many worlds interpretation or Bohmian mechanics” (p. 4). First of all, this isn’t true–neither Bohmian mechanics nor many worlds needs a privileged observer. Indeed, as Dustin Lazarovici points out the physicist John Bell of the Bell inequality called both Bohmian mechanics and many worlds “quantum theories without an observer.”
After this remark the scientists immediately shift to the thesis of their paper: that we should give up an observer independent reality. However, as we saw, there is no need to do this–we already have theories that account for this! As Wayne Myrvold remarks :
“Here’s a nice fact about claims of this sort: when you see one, you can be sure, without even going through the details of the argument, that any conclusion to the effect that the predictions of quantum mechanics are incompatible with an objective, observer-independent reality, is simply and plainly false. That is because we have a theory that yields all of the predictions of standard quantum mechanics and coherently describes a single, observer-independent world. This is the theory that was presented already in 1927 by Louis de Broglie, and was rediscovered in 1952 by David Bohm, and is either called the de Broglie-Bohm pilot wave theory, or Bohmian mechanics, depending on who you’re talking to. You can be confident that, if you went through the details of any real or imagined experiment, then you would find that the de Broglie-Bohm theory gives a consistent, observer-independent, one-world account of what happens in the experiment, an account that is in complete accord with standard quantum mechanics with regards to predictions of experimental outcomes.
There are other theories, known as dynamical collapse theories, that also yield accounts of a single, observer-independent reality. These theories yield virtually the same predictions as standard quantum mechanics for all experiments that are currently feasible, but differ from the predictions of quantum mechanics for some experiments involving macroscopic objects.”
He doesn’t mention Everttian (many worlds) quantum mechanics in this passage, but it too is compatible with this result. As Sean Carroll in the same Daily Nous piece puts it:
“My own preferred version of quantum mechanics is the Everett, or Many-Worlds formulation. It is a thoroughly realist theory, and is completely compatible with the experimental results obtained here. Thus, we have a proof by construction that this result cannot possibly imply that there is no objective reality.”
What we have to do in order to keep observer-independent facts is to give up a strong form of locality. Pretty much all of our theories of quantum mechanics give up locality. But we already knew this! It is old news. (Subtle side note: even though Everettian quantum mechanics and GRW flashes are non-local in the sense needed to give the standard quantum mechanical predictions, they are still (very likely) compatible with special relativity. This is not essential for our story here, but is worth mentioning.) Indeed, as Tim Maudlin remarks (you already know whence this quote comes!):
“All of this is even spelled out in the article itself: ‘But there are other assumptions too. One is that observers have the freedom to make whatever observations they want. And another is that the choices one observer makes do not influence the choices other observers make—an assumption that physicists call locality.’ That is, in order to account for the outcome of this experiment, one has to deny that physical reality is local in Bell’s sense. (This gloss on the locality condition is not accurate, but leave that aside.) That is something we have known for 50 years.”
Thus we see that the experimental results really show nothing new, and certainly nothing that should make us question objective reality. It really does seem to be an unfortunate case of physicists either being confused, or trying to sell their result too much (inclusive or!). The most charitable reading of these results I could find is by Karen Crowther whom I referenced earlier:
“The question is what this experiment demonstrates about QM that was not already known from the thought-experiment plus previous experimental results. Plausibly, what it shows is that a scenario analogous to the one imagined by Wigner is in fact physically possible, and in it the observers do record conflicting facts.”
The least charitable (but also very amusing) quote I encountered was from Dustin Lazarovici:
“In my opinion, the paper does indeed raise some important questions, though they are mostly sociological ones. For instance: Why does physics tend to get exposure and attention merely for making outlandish claims, regardless of their scientific substance? And why do even many experts tend to abandon rational and critical standards when it comes to quantum mechanics? Why, in other words, have we gotten so used to quantum physics being crazy that even the most outlandish claims come with a presupposition of plausibility and relevance?
As a matter of fact, quantum mechanics can be as clear and rational as any respectable theory that came before it. You just have to do it right.”
I have to agree with this sentiment. Although, as for his first question, I think we can explain that by noticing that humans tend to be more interested in outlandish claims like “THERE IS NO OBJECTIVE REALITY”. Again, no one wants to read the paper entitled “K-alpha particles exhibit decoherence along mesa-keta spectra at 196mmz intervals”. It’s not sexy enough to rise to the surface of the MIT Technology Review.
I think the message to take away from all of this is that objective reality is fine, and nothing has really changed at all in quantum mechanics because of this result. I’ll give the last words to Wayne Myrvold:
“Headline news! Stop the presses! A group of experimenters did an experiment, and the results came out exactly the way that our best physical theory of such things says it should, just as everyone expected. Quantum Theory Confirmed Again .
That’s what actually happened, though you’d never know it from the clickbait headline: A quantum experiment suggests there’s no such thing as objective reality .”
Share this:
2 thoughts on “paper review: experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world”.
Ha! Thanks for the breakdown, Daniel!
I was just going to ask you about this in person; it’s great to be able to go to your blog to find your thoughts like this.
Looking forward to hearing your thoughts for years to come!
Yes, I too — many shared years, many shared thoughts!
Leave a comment Cancel reply
- Already have a WordPress.com account? Log in now.
- Subscribe Subscribed
- Copy shortlink
- Report this content
- View post in Reader
- Manage subscriptions
- Collapse this bar
Experimental test of local observer-independence
The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally, independently of who observed them. In quantum mechanics, the objectivity of observations is not so clear, most dramatically exposed in Eugene Wigner’s eponymous thought experiment where two observers can experience seemingly different realities. The question whether these realities can be reconciled in an observer-independent way has long remained inaccessible to empirical investigation, until recent no-go-theorems constructed an extended Wigner’s friend scenario with four observers that allows us to put it to the test. In a state-of-the-art 6-photon experiment, we realise this extended Wigner’s friend scenario, experimentally violating the associated Bell-type inequality by 5 standard deviations. If one holds fast to the assumptions of locality and free-choice, this result implies that quantum theory should be interpreted in an observer-dependent way.
Introduction.—
The observer’s role as final arbiter of universal facts Popper ( 1992 ) was imperilled by the advent of 20 th th {}^{\textrm{th}} century science. In relativity, previously absolute observations are now relative to moving reference frames; in quantum theory, all physical processes are continuous and deterministic, except for observations, which are proclaimed to be instantaneous and probabilistic. This fundamental conflict in quantum theory is known as the measurement problem, and it originates because the theory does not provide a clear cut between a process being a measurement or just another unitary physical interaction.
This is best illustrated in the seminal “Wigner’s friend” thought experiment Wigner ( 1961 ) , whose far-reaching implications are only starting to become clear Brukner ( 2015 , 2018 ); Frauchiger and Renner ( 2018 ) . Consider a single photon in a superposition of horizontal | h ⟩ ket ℎ |h\rangle and vertical polarisation | v ⟩ ket 𝑣 |v\rangle , measured in the { | h ⟩ , | v ⟩ } ket ℎ ket 𝑣 \{|h\rangle,|v\rangle\} -basis by an observer—Wigner’s friend—in an isolated lab, see Figs. 1 a and b . According to quantum theory, the friend randomly observes one of the two possible outcomes in every run of the experiment. The friend’s record, h ℎ h or v 𝑣 v , can be stored in one of two possible orthogonal states of some physical memory, labeled either | “photon is h ” ⟩ ket “photon is h ” |\text{``photon is {h}''}\rangle or | “photon is v ” ⟩ ket “photon is v ” |\text{``photon is {v}''}\rangle , and constitutes a “fact” from the friend’s point of view. Wigner, who observes the isolated laboratory from the outside, has no information about his friend’s measurement outcome. According to quantum theory Wigner must describe the friend’s measurement as a unitary interaction that leaves the photon and friend’s record in the entangled state (with implicit tensor products):
(1) |
Wigner can now perform an interference experiment in an entangled basis containing the states of Eq. ( 1 ) to verify that the photon and his friend’s record are indeed in a superposition—a “fact” from his point of view. From this fact, Wigner concludes that his friend cannot have recorded a definite outcome. Concurrently however, the friend does always record a definite outcome, which suggests that the original superposition was destroyed and Wigner should not observe any interference. The friend can even tell Wigner that she recorded a definite outcome (without revealing the result), yet Wigner and his friend’s respective descriptions remain unchanged Deutsch ( 1985 ) . This calls into question the objective status of the facts established by the two observers. Can one reconcile their different records, or are they fundamentally incompatible—so that they cannot be considered objective, observer-independent “facts of the world” Brukner ( 2015 , 2018 ) ?
(2) |
As shown in Refs. Brukner ( 2015 , 2018 ) , a violation of the inequality above is, however, possible in a physical world described by quantum theory. Such a violation would demonstrate that the observed probability distributions P ( A x , B y ) 𝑃 subscript 𝐴 𝑥 subscript 𝐵 𝑦 P(A_{x},B_{y}) are incompatible with assumptions F, L, and O. Therefore, if we accept F and L, it follows that the pieces of information corresponding to facts established by Alice, Bob, and their friends cannot coexist within a single, observer-independent framework Brukner ( 2015 , 2018 ) . Notably this is the case even though Alice and Bob can acknowledge the occurrence of a definite outcome in their friend’s closed laboratory.
We note that, although Bell’s mathematical machinery Bell and Aspect ( 2004 ) is used to show the result, the set of assumptions considered here—and therefore the conclusions that can be drawn from a violation of inequality ( 2 )—are different from those in standard Bell tests. In fact, while they share assumptions L and F, the third assumption of predetermination (PD) in the original Bell theorem Bell ( 1964 ) , for instance, differs from our assumption O in that it is only concerned with the deterministic (or otherwise) nature of measurement outcomes, not with their objectivity as in O. A Bell test is indifferent to the observables used and the underlying system, such that any violation suffices to rule out the conjunction of L, F and PD. In contrast, a Bell-Wigner test is based on very specific observables that satisfy the definition of an observation given below and thus represent facts relative to different observers. Formally, any Bell-Wigner violation implies a Bell-violation, but not the other way round.
Before we describe our experiment in which we test and indeed violate inequality ( 2 ), let us first clarify our notion of an observer. Formally, an observation is the act of extracting and storing information about an observed system. Accordingly, we define an observer as any physical system that can extract information from another system by means of some interaction, and store that information in a physical memory.
Such an observer can establish “facts”, to which we assign the value recorded in their memory. Notably, the formalism of quantum mechanics does not make a distinction between large (even conscious) and small physical systems, which is sometimes referred to as universality. Hence, our definition covers human observers, as well as more commonly used non-conscious observers such as (classical or quantum) computers and other measurement devices—even the simplest possible ones, as long as they satisfy the above requirements. We note that the no-go theorem formulated in Frauchiger and Renner ( 2018 ) requires observers to be “agents”, who “use” quantum theory to make predictions based on the measurement outcomes. In contrast, for the no-go theorem we tested here Brukner ( 2018 ) it is sufficient that they perform a measurement and record the outcome. The enhanced capabilities required of agents were recently discussed in Baumann and Brukner ( 2019 ) .
0.02 0.10 \mathcal{C}=99.38^{+0.02}_{-0.10}\% , see Supplementary Materials for details. The photon pair from source S 0 subscript 𝑆 0 S_{0} is rotated to
(3) |
To test inequality ( 2 ), Alice and Bob then measure the following observables on their respective joint photon / friend’s record systems:
| ||||
(4) |
(with | Φ photon/record ± ⟩ ket subscript superscript Φ plus-or-minus photon/record |\Phi^{\pm}_{\text{photon/record}}\rangle as defined in Eq. ( 1 )). The observables A 0 subscript 𝐴 0 A_{0} and B 0 subscript 𝐵 0 B_{0} directly unveil the records established by Alice’s and Bob’s friend, respectively. The observables A 1 subscript 𝐴 1 A_{1} and B 1 subscript 𝐵 1 B_{1} , on the other hand, correspond to Alice’s and Bob’s joint measurements on their friend’s photon and record, and define their own facts in the same way as Wigner in the original thought experiment confirms his entangled state assignment.
0.075 0.075 S_{\textrm{exp}}=2.416^{+0.075}_{-0.075} , thus violating inequality ( 2 ) by more than 5 5 5 standard deviations. This value is primarily limited by the higher-order photon emissions from our probabilistic photon sources. Statistical uncertainties are independently estimated using an error propagation approach and a Monte-Carlo method. Details are discussed in the Supplementary Materials.
Discussion.—
One might further be tempted to deny our photonic memories the status of “observer”. This, however, would require a convincing revision of our minimal definition of what qualifies as an observer, which typically comes at the cost of introducing new physics that is not described by standard quantum theory. Eugene Wigner, for example, argued that the disagreement with his hypothetical friend could not arise due to a supposed impossibility for conscious observers to be in a superposition state Wigner ( 1961 ) . However, the lack of objectivity revealed by a Bell-Wigner test does not arise in anyone’s consciousness, but between the recorded facts. Since quantum theory does not distinguish between information recorded in a microscopic system (such as our photonic memory) and in a macroscopic system the conclusions are the same for both: the measurement records are in conflict regardless of the size or complexity of the observer that records them. Implementing the experiment with more complex observers would not necessarily lead to new insights into the specific issue of observer-independence in quantum theory. It would however serve to show that quantum mechanics still holds at larger scales, ruling out alternative (collapse) models Ghirardi et al. ( 1986 ) . However, this is not the point of a Bell-Wigner test—less demanding experiments could show that.
Modulo the potential loopholes and accepting the photons’ status as observers, the violation of inequality ( 2 ) implies that at least one of the three assumptions of free choice, locality, and observer-independent facts must fail. The related no-go theorem by Frauchiger & Renner Frauchiger and Renner ( 2018 ) rests on different assumptions which do not explicitly include locality. While the precise interpretation of Ref. Frauchiger and Renner ( 2018 ) within non-local theories is under debate Lazarovici and Hubert ( 2019 ) , it seems that abandoning free choice and locality might not resolve the contradiction Frauchiger and Renner ( 2018 ) . A compelling way to accommodate our result is then to proclaim that “facts of the world” can only be established by a privileged observer—e.g., one that would have access to the “global wavefunction” in the many worlds interpretation Everett ( 1957 ) or Bohmian mechanics Bohm ( 1952 ) . Another option is to give up observer independence completely by considering facts only relative to observers Rovelli ( 1996 ) , or by adopting an interpretation such as QBism, where quantum mechanics is just a tool that captures an agent’s subjective prediction of future measurement outcomes Fuchs ( 2017 ) . This choice, however, requires us to embrace the possibility that different observers irreconcilably disagree about what happened in an experiment. A further interesting question is whether the conclusions drawn from Bell-, or Bell-Wigner tests change under relativistic conditions with non-inertial observers Durham ( 2019 ) .
- Popper (1992) K. Popper, Realism and the Aim of Science (Routledge, 1992).
- Wigner (1961) E. Wigner, in The Scientist Speculates , edited by I. Good (1961), pp. 284–302.
- Brukner (2015) Č. Brukner, arXiv:1507.05255 (2015).
- Brukner (2018) Č. Brukner, Entropy 20 , 350 (2018).
- Frauchiger and Renner (2018) D. Frauchiger and R. Renner, Nature communications 9 , 3711 (2018).
- Deutsch (1985) D. Deutsch, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 24 , 1 (1985).
- Healey (2018) R. Healey, Found. Phys. 48 , 1568 (2018).
- Baumann et al. (2019) V. Baumann, F. Del Santo, and Č. Brukner, Found. Phys. 49 , 741 (2019).
- Fine (1982) A. Fine, Phys. Rev. Lett. 48 , 291 (1982).
- Clauser et al. (1969) J. Clauser, M. Horne, A. Shimony, and R. Holt, Phys. Rev. Lett. 23 , 880 (1969).
- Bell and Aspect (2004) J. S. Bell and A. Aspect, Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics: Collected Papers on Quantum Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 2004), 2nd ed.
- Bell (1964) J. S. Bell, Physics 1 , 195 (1964).
- Baumann and Brukner (2019) V. Baumann and Č. Brukner, arXiv:1901.11274 (2019).
- Graffitti et al. (2018a) F. Graffitti, P. Barrow, M. Proietti, D. Kundys, and A. Fedrizzi, Optica 5 , 514 (2018a).
- Graffitti et al. (2018b) F. Graffitti, J. Kelly-Massicotte, A. Fedrizzi, and A. M. Brańczyk, Phys. Rev. A 98 , 053811 (2018b).
- Jin et al. (2014) R.-B. Jin, R. Shimizu, K. Wakui, M. Fujiwara, T. Yamashita, S. Miki, H. Terai, Z. Wang, and M. Sasaki, Opt. Express 22 , 11498 (2014).
- Browne and Rudolph (2005) D. E. Browne and T. Rudolph, Phys. Rev. Lett. 95 , 010501 (2005).
- Pan et al. (2001) J.-W. Pan, M. Daniell, S. Gasparoni, G. Weihs, and A. Zeilinger, Phys. Rev. Lett. 86 , 4435 (2001).
- Larsson (2014) J.-Å. Larsson, J. Phys. A 47 , 424003 (2014).
- Ghirardi et al. (1986) G. C. Ghirardi, A. Rimini, and T. Weber, Phys. Rev. D 34 , 470 (1986).
- Lazarovici and Hubert (2019) D. Lazarovici and M. Hubert, Sci. Rep. 9 , 470 (2019).
- Everett (1957) H. I. Everett, Rev. Mod. Phys. 29 , 454 (1957).
- Bohm (1952) D. Bohm, Phys. Rev. 85 , 166 (1952).
- Rovelli (1996) C. Rovelli, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 35 , 1637 (1996).
- Fuchs (2017) C. A. Fuchs, Mind and Matter 15 , 245 (2017).
- Durham (2019) I. T. Durham, arXiv:1902.09028 (2019).
- Fedrizzi et al. (2007) A. Fedrizzi, T. Herbst, A. Poppe, T. Jennewein, and A. Zeilinger, Opt. Express 15 , 15377 (2007).
- Broome et al. (2011) M. A. Broome, M. P. Almeida, A. Fedrizzi, and A. G. White, Opt. Express 19 , 22698 (2011).
- Calsamiglia and Lutkenhaus (2001) J. Calsamiglia and N. Lutkenhaus, Appl. Phys. B 72 , 67 (2001).
- Braunstein and Mann (1995) S. L. Braunstein and A. Mann, Phys. Rev. A 51 , R1727 (1995).
- Eberhard (1993) P. H. Eberhard, Phys. Rev. A 47 , 747 (1993).
Acknowledgements We thank Č. Brukner, R. Renner and F. Shahandeh for useful discussions. This work was supported by the UK Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council (grant number EP/N002962/1, EP/L015110/1) and the French National Research Agency (grant number ANR-13-PDOC-0026). This project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant agreement No 801110 and the Austrian Federal Ministry of Education, Science and Research (BMBWF).
Correspondence Correspondence and requests for materials should be addressed to AF (email: [email protected]).
Supplementary materials
Setup details.—.
Measurement protocol.—
We now describe in detail the measurement procedure sketched in Fig. 2 . Source S 0 subscript 𝑆 0 S_{0} and the HWP on its right output arm produce an entangled pair of photons in the state of Eq. ( 3 ). This photon pair is distributed to the laboratories of Alice’s friend and Bob’s friend, who measure their photon using Type-I fusion gates Browne and Rudolph ( 2005 ) . Each fusion gate is implemented with a PBS, where horizontally and vertically polarised photons are transmitted and reflected, respectively (by convention collecting a phase i 𝑖 i for the latter). Two photons entering the PBS from two different inputs with opposite polarisation, | h ⟩ | v ⟩ ket ℎ ket 𝑣 |h\rangle|v\rangle or | v ⟩ | h ⟩ ket 𝑣 ket ℎ |v\rangle|h\rangle , will exit from the same output port, and will therefore not lead to coincident detection. Only the coincident | h ⟩ | h ⟩ ket ℎ ket ℎ |h\rangle|h\rangle and | v ⟩ | v ⟩ ket 𝑣 ket 𝑣 |v\rangle|v\rangle components will be recorded in post-selection. For these post-selected photons, the fusion gate induces the following transformations:
(S1) |
where Q/HWP refers to the combination of a quarter-wave plate at π / 4 𝜋 4 \pi/4 and a half-wave plate at π / 8 𝜋 8 \pi/8 behind the PBS (see Fig. 2 ). The second (heralding) photon in the above equation is then projected onto the state | h ⟩ ket ℎ |h\rangle via another PBS. The Type-I fusion gate thus implements the operation
(S2) |
where the factor 1 2 1 2 \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} indicates the success probability of the gate of 1 2 1 2 \frac{1}{2} .
To use the fusion gate to measure photon a 𝑎 a (see Fig. 2 ) non-destructively, Alice’s friend uses an ancilla from the entangled pair created by S A subscript 𝑆 𝐴 S_{A} , prepared as | Ψ − ⟩ α ′ α subscript ket superscript Ψ superscript 𝛼 ′ 𝛼 |\Psi^{-}\rangle_{\alpha^{\prime}\alpha} . Depending on the state of the incoming photon, the operation performed by Alice’s friend transforms the overall state as
(S3) |
Hence, the state | h ⟩ a subscript ket ℎ 𝑎 |h\rangle_{a} or | v ⟩ a subscript ket 𝑣 𝑎 |v\rangle_{a} of the external photon in mode a 𝑎 a is copied, after being flipped ( h ↔ v ↔ ℎ 𝑣 h\leftrightarrow v ), onto Alice’s friend’s photon in mode α 𝛼 \alpha . In other words, this corresponds to a measurement of the incoming photon in the { h , v } ℎ 𝑣 \{h,v\} -basis, with the outcome being recorded in the state of photon α 𝛼 \alpha , such that we can write
(S4) |
The amplitudes 1 2 1 2 \frac{1}{2} in Eq. ( S3 ) indicate the total success probability of 1 4 1 4 \frac{1}{4} for this procedure.
Consider now the central source S 0 subscript 𝑆 0 S_{0} together with Alice’s and Bob’s friends’ laboratories. According to Eq. ( 3 ), the state generated by S 0 subscript 𝑆 0 S_{0} is, after the unitary U 7 π 16 subscript 𝑈 7 𝜋 16 U_{\frac{7\pi}{16}} ,
(S5) |
The transformations induced by Alice’s and Bob’s friends are then, according to Eq. ( S3 ):
(S6) |
with a global success probability of 1 16 1 16 \frac{1}{16} . The state
(S7) |
is the four-photon state shared by Alice and Bob when both fusion gates are successful.
Recalling from Eq. ( S4 ) how the friends’ measurement results are encoded in their polarisation states, the observables of Eq. ( 4 ) to be measured on | Ψ ~ ′ ⟩ a α b β subscript ket superscript ~ Ψ ′ 𝑎 𝛼 𝑏 𝛽 |\tilde{\Psi}^{\prime}\rangle_{a\alpha b\beta} are
| (S8) |
1 1 2 0.427 \frac{1}{4}(1+\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}})\simeq 0.427 , 1 4 ( 1 − 1 2 ) ≃ 0.073 similar-to-or-equals 1 4 1 1 2 0.073 \frac{1}{4}(1-\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}})\simeq 0.073 , or 0 0 . In addition to this result, an alternative measurement protocol for A 0 subscript 𝐴 0 A_{0} and B 0 subscript 𝐵 0 B_{0} is presented below.
Error analysis.—
As described previously, each average value ⟨ A x B y ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 𝑥 subscript 𝐵 𝑦 \langle A_{x}B_{y}\rangle is calculated from 16 measured 6-fold coincidence counts n i subscript 𝑛 𝑖 n_{i} . These numbers follow a Poisson distribution with variance σ n i 2 = n i superscript subscript 𝜎 subscript 𝑛 𝑖 2 subscript 𝑛 𝑖 \sigma_{n_{i}}^{2}=n_{i} . The uncertainty on ⟨ A x B y ⟩ = f ( n 1 , … , n 16 ) delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 𝑥 subscript 𝐵 𝑦 𝑓 subscript 𝑛 1 … subscript 𝑛 16 \langle A_{x}B_{y}\rangle=f(n_{1},\ldots,n_{16}) can then be computed using
(S9) |
Since the four averages ⟨ A 1 B 1 ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 1 subscript 𝐵 1 \langle A_{1}B_{1}\rangle , ⟨ A 1 B 0 ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 1 subscript 𝐵 0 \langle A_{1}B_{0}\rangle , ⟨ A 0 B 1 ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 0 subscript 𝐵 1 \langle A_{0}B_{1}\rangle and ⟨ A 0 B 0 ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 0 subscript 𝐵 0 \langle A_{0}B_{0}\rangle are statistically independent, the uncertainties can be calculated independently and combined to estimate the uncertainty on S 𝑆 S . To take into account potentially asymmetric errors in the limit of small count rates, we computed the uncertainty on the Bell-Wigner parameter S 𝑆 S using a Monte-Carlo routine with 100 000 samples. The values obtained through these two methods agree to within 0.0032 0.0032 0.0032 .
Note that in the results shown in Fig. S3 with the observables of Eq. ( S10 ), errors are correlated due to normalisation with a common total. Accounting for this in the error propagation results in slightly larger statistical uncertainty.
The Bell-Wigner value S e x p subscript 𝑆 𝑒 𝑥 𝑝 S_{exp} that can be achieved experimentally is primarily limited by multi-pair emissions from our probabilistic photon-pair sources. We first note that any emission of 3 pairs from any subset of our 3 sources occurs with roughly similar probability. To exclude unwanted terms we use six-fold coincidence detection, which can only be successful for an emission of one pair each in S 0 subscript 𝑆 0 S_{0} , S A subscript 𝑆 𝐴 S_{A} and S B subscript 𝑆 𝐵 S_{B} , or three pairs in S 0 subscript 𝑆 0 S_{0} . The latter would amount to noise but is excluded by our cross-polarisation design and can thus not lead to a coincidence detection. This leaves higher-order contributions where at least 4 photon pairs are produced as the main source of errors. Since such events scale with a higher exponent of the pump power, they are suppressed in our experiment by working with a relatively low pump power of 100 mW.
Towards a loophole-free “Bell-Wigner” test.—
Since our experiment relies on some of the same assumptions as traditional Bell tests, it is subject to the same conceptual and technical loopholes: locality, freedom of choice, and the detection loophole. Due to the increased complexity of our experiment, compared to a standard Bell test, the practical requirements for closing these loopholes are significantly more challenging. We now briefly discuss how these loopholes could be closed in the future.
The configuration of our experiment makes it analogous to an “event-ready” Bell test, where the detection of the ancilla photons in the fusion gates heralds which events should be kept for the Bell-Wigner test. In such a configuration, closing the locality and freedom of choice loopholes requires the heralding events to be space-like separated from Alice’s and Bob’s setting choices, which should each be space-like separated from the measurement outcome of the other party. This imposes stringent space-time location requirements for a Bell-Wigner test closing these loopholes.
The detection loophole arises because only a fraction of all created photons is detected. In our “event-ready” configuration, the limited success probability of the fusion gates is not an issue: only heralded events will contribute to the Bell-Wigner test. Nevertheless, to ensure that the fusion gates are indeed event-ready, the ancilla detectors should be photon-number-resolving.
ket superscript Ψ |\Psi^{+}\rangle,|\Psi^{-}\rangle , and have a third outcome for | Φ ± ⟩ ket superscript Φ plus-or-minus |\Phi^{\pm}\rangle (see Eq. ( S8 )). This can be realised with a small modification to our setup, with detectors added on the second outputs of Alice’s and Bob’s PBS Braunstein and Mann ( 1995 ) . An even simpler measurement would discriminate e.g. | Ψ − ⟩ ket superscript Ψ |\Psi^{-}\rangle from the other three Bell states, thus measuring the observables A 1 = B 1 = 𝟙 − 2 | Ψ − ⟩ ⟨ Ψ − | subscript 𝐴 1 subscript 𝐵 1 1 2 ket superscript Ψ bra superscript Ψ A_{1}=B_{1}=\mathds{1}-2|\Psi^{-}\rangle\!\langle\Psi^{-}| ; this would not change anything in an ideal implementation, but simplifies the analysis with detection inefficiencies below.
superscript 𝜂 4 1 2 superscript 1 superscript 𝜂 2 2 \langle A_{1}B_{1}\rangle=\eta^{4}\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}+(1-\eta^{2})^{2} . With these values, the minimal required detection efficiency to violate inequality ( 2 ) with (unrealistically) perfect quantum states and measurements is η > 2 3 ( 1 − 1 2 ) − 1 ≃ 0.875 𝜂 2 3 1 1 2 1 similar-to-or-equals 0.875 \eta>2\sqrt{3(1-\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}})}-1\simeq 0.875 . This is a more stringent requirement than for a standard test of the CHSH inequality, for which a similar analysis for maximally entangled states yields η > 2 2 − 2 ≃ 0.828 𝜂 2 2 2 similar-to-or-equals 0.828 \eta>2\sqrt{2}-2\simeq 0.828 . To relax this requirement, one might attempt similar tricks as for standard Bell tests, e.g. to use non-maximally entangled states Eberhard ( 1993 ) , although this will come at the cost of a reduced violation of the inequality.
Note, finally, that in the conclusions we draw from the violation of inequality ( 2 ), we need to trust that A 0 subscript 𝐴 0 A_{0} and B 0 subscript 𝐵 0 B_{0} indeed directly measure the memory of Alice’s and Bob’s friends, so as to unveil their respective facts. A new loophole may be opened, now specific to Bell-Wigner tests, if such an interpretation cannot be maintained. To address this loophole with a setup like ours, one should use measurement devices for A 0 subscript 𝐴 0 A_{0} and B 0 subscript 𝐵 0 B_{0} that clearly separate the initial systems and the memories of each friend, and only “looks” at the memory photons, rather than at the system photon + memory photon together; we also leave this possibility as a challenge for future Bell-Wigner experimental tests.
Alternative observables A 0 , B 0 subscript 𝐴 0 subscript 𝐵 0 A_{0},B_{0} .—
(S10) |
which have a slightly different physical interpretation. The observables used in the main text and defined in Eq. ( 4 ), directly measure the facts established by the friend, as recorded in their memory. In contrast, the observables in Eq. ( S10 ) can be understood as not only a measurement of the friend’s record (to establish a “fact for the friend”), but also of the original photon measured by the friend, as a consistency check: if the state of the photon is found to be inconsistent with the friend’s record, the definition above assigns a value 0 0 for the measurement result.
0.073 0.073 S_{exp}=2.407^{+0.073}_{-0.073} , again violating inequality ( 2 ) by more than 5 standard deviations. As in the main text, errors are computed assuming Poissonian photon counting statistics, see below for details.
Alternative measurement protocol for A 0 , B 0 subscript 𝐴 0 subscript 𝐵 0 A_{0},B_{0} .—
Recall that in order to measure A 0 subscript 𝐴 0 A_{0} (similarly B 0 subscript 𝐵 0 B_{0} ), the beam splitter for Alice in Fig. 2 has to be removed relative to the measurement of A 1 subscript 𝐴 1 A_{1} . A less invasive method (which does not compromise the alignment of our optical elements) is to introduce linear polarisers in modes a ( b ) 𝑎 𝑏 a(b) and α ( β ) 𝛼 𝛽 \alpha(\beta) . This effectively measures the photons before the BS, preventing interference.
0.110 0.110 S_{exp}=2.346^{+0.110}_{-0.110} , violating the Bell-Wigner inequality by more than 3 standard deviations. We note that the violation observed with this method is somewhat reduced because of ∼ 4.83 ± 0.97 % similar-to absent plus-or-minus 4.83 percent 0.97 \sim 4.83\pm 0.97\% loss that is introduced by the polarisers. This effectively reduces the number of counts that are observed in the settings A 0 subscript 𝐴 0 A_{0} and B 0 subscript 𝐵 0 B_{0} compared to the normalisation used, and thereby reduces the expectation values ⟨ A 0 B 1 ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 0 subscript 𝐵 1 \langle A_{0}B_{1}\rangle and ⟨ A 1 B 0 ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 1 subscript 𝐵 0 \langle A_{1}B_{0}\rangle , and ⟨ A 0 B 0 ⟩ delimited-⟨⟩ subscript 𝐴 0 subscript 𝐵 0 \langle A_{0}B_{0}\rangle , leading to a reduced violation.
COMMENTS
Quantum Physics. Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world. The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally, independently of who observed them. In quantum mechanics, the objectivity of observations is not so clear, most dramatically exposed in Eugene Wigner ...
While observer-independence has long remained inaccessible to empirical investigation, recent no-go-theorems construct an extended Wigner's friend scenario with four entangled observers that allows us to put it to the test. In a state-of-the-art 6-photon experiment, we here realise this extended Wigner's friend scenario, experimentally ...
Request PDF | Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world | The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally ...
Implementing the experiment with more complex observers would not necessarily lead to new insights into the specific issue of observer-independence in quantum theory. It would however serve to show that quantum mechanics still holds at larger scales, ruling out alternative (collapse) models [16].
Physicists have long suspected that quantum mechanics allows two observers to experience different, conflicting realities. ... Experimental Rejection of Observer-Independence ... who went to ...
Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world Massimiliano Proietti, 1Alexander Pickston, Francesco Graffitti, Peter Barrow,1 Dmytro Kundys,1 Cyril Branciard,2 Martin Ringbauer,1,3 and Alessandro Fedrizzi1 1Scottish Universities Physics Alliance (SUPA), Institute of Photonics and Quantum Sciences, School of Engineering and Physical Sciences, Heriot-Watt University ...
When Eugene Wigner conceived his Gedanken experiment in 1961 [1], he argued that in quantum theory two observers, Wigner and his friend, can experience two fundamentally different descriptions of reality. Yet, only six decades later, this question has been rigorously tackled independently by Brukner [2] and Frauchiger and Renner [3], leveraging on the Bell's theorem and on the Hardy's Paradox ...
3. "Freedom of choice". The choice of measurement settings is statistically independent from the rest of the experiment. 4. "Observer-independent facts". One can jointly assign truth values to the propositions about observed outcomes ("facts") of different observers (as specified in the postulate above).
Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world (30'+10') Tuesday, 30 April 2019 15:40 (0:40) Content Summary Presenter(s) : A. FEDRIZZI (Heriot-Watt University Edinburgh, UK) Session Classi cation : DAY II. Created Date:
This result lends considerable strength to interpretations of quantum theory already set in an observer-dependent framework and demands for revision of those which are not.}, added-at = {2019-04-09T14:43:35.000+0200}, author = {Proietti, Massimiliano and Pickston, Alexander and Graffitti, Francesco and Barrow, Peter and Kundys, Dmytro and ...
Experimental test of local observer-independence Massimiliano Proietti, 1Alexander Pickston, Francesco Graffitti, Peter Barrow,1 Dmytro Kundys,1 Cyril Branciard,2 Martin Ringbauer,1,3 and Alessandro Fedrizzi1 1Scottish Universities Physics Alliance (SUPA), Institute of Photonics and Quantum Sciences, School of Engineering and Physical Sciences, Heriot-Watt University, Edinburgh EH14 4AS, UK.
unitary quantum mechanics. Since A0 and A1 do not commute, they are not expected to have simultaneous values. Proietti et al. [2] interpret their result as an "experimental rejection of observer-independence." If one observer registers a value, the other doesn't. To reach this conclusion, they are careful to define an observer as "any ...
According to quantum theory, Wigner must describe the friend s measurement as a unitary interaction that leaves the photon ' and the friends record in the entangled state (with implicit tensor ' products) 1 1. ± photon is. ffiffiffi2 ð∣h〉 ∣v〉Þ→ p ffiffiffi2 ð∣h〉∣" h"〉. ± ∣v〉∣"photon is ± v"〉Þ≕∣F ...
"Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world" Uh-oh. This sounds like a case where maybe the media are actually reporting accurately on the science—the title would certainly suggest that the scientists believe their experiment rejects objective reality, or something like that.
The observer's role as final arbiter of universal facts was imperiled by the advent of 20th century science.In relativity, previously absolute observations are now relative to moving reference frames; in quantum theory, all physical processes are continuous and deterministic, except for observations, which are proclaimed to be instantaneous and probabilistic.
The observer's role as final arbiter of universal facts Popper was imperilled by the advent of 20 th th {}^{\textrm{th}} century science. In relativity, previously absolute observations are now relative to moving reference frames; in quantum theory, all physical processes are continuous and deterministic, except for observations, which are proclaimed to be instantaneous and probabilistic.
Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world (arxiv.org) 187 points by lisper 7 months ago | hide | past ... So an "experimental demonstration" of their setup—by which one really means an experimental demonstration of Hardy's experiment, since the Frauchiger-Renner one would require superposed conscious observers ...
2018. TLDR. A no-go theorem for observer-independent facts, which would be common both for Wigner and the friend is derived and is analyzed in the context of a newly-derived theorem arXiv:1604.07422, where Frauchiger and Renner prove that "single-world interpretations of quantum theory cannot be self-consistent". Expand.
Only if you assume locality holds fast. This subs ideas already reject the idea of locality and much of quantum research is leaning the same way (quantum eraser experiment). To me, this only corroborates a non local observer independent universe, not disproves it. What this experiment does is violate the bell inequality.
Experimental quantum conference key agreement. M Proietti, J Ho, F Grasselli, P Barrow, M Malik, A Fedrizzi ... Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world. arXiv e-prints, page. M Proietti, A Pickston, F Graffitti, P Barrow, D Kundys, C Branciard, ... arXiv preprint arXiv:1902.05080, 2019. 2: 2019: Experimental test of ...
Observer-independence in the presence of a horizon. Ian T. Durham. In the famous thought experiment known as Wigner's friend, Wigner assigns an entangled state to the composite quantum system consisting of his friend and her observed system. In the context of this thought experiment, Brukner recently derived a no-go theorem for observer ...
Experimental rejection of observer-independence in the quantum world. Massimiliano Proietti, Alexander Pickston, Francesco Graffitti, Peter Barrow, Dmytro Kundys, Cyril Branciard, Martin Ringbauer ...
The results can be interpreted to imply that in quantum physics the objectivity of facts is not absolute, but only relative to the observation and the observer. The objective world
In DC microgrids, a large-capacity hybrid energy storage system (HESS) is introduced to eliminate variable fluctuations of distributed source powers and load powers. Aiming at improving disturbance immunity and decreasing adjustment time, this paper proposes active disturbance rejection control (ADRC) combined with improved MPC for n + 1 parallel converters of large-capacity hybrid energy ...